1585 Stevin introduces decimal numbers. (For example, writing 1/8 as 0.125) 1637 Cartesian geometry published by Fermat and Descartes 1684 Leibniz publishes The Calculus 1761 Lambert proves that Pi is irrational 1821 Cauchy publishes the "epsilon-delta" definition of a limit, which brought rigor to The Calculus. 1830 Galois publishes "Galois Theory", which explains why a general polynomial equation of order n can be solved in terms of radicals only if n <= 4. 1844 Louisville proves the existence of transcendental numbers 1851 Louisville constructs the first transcendental number 1854 Riemann publishes the Riemann Integral, the first rigorous definition of an integral. 1859 Riemann Hypothesis published 1860 Grassmann studies the question of the axiomatization of arithmetic. 1870 Heine defines "uniform continuity" 1872 Heine proves that a continuous function on an open interval need not be uniformly continuous. 1872 Weierstrass publishes the "Weierstrass function", the first example of a function that is continuous everywhere but differentiable nowhere. 1873 Hermite proves that "e" is transcendental 1874 Cantor proves that the algebraic numbers are countable and that the real numbers are uncountable, using the "diagonal slash" argument. 1874 Cantor publishes the first attempt at a rigorous set theory. 1878 Cantor proves that the transcendental numbers and the real numbers have the same cardinality, thus estabilishing the ubiquity of transcendental numbers 1878 Cantor publishes the "Continuum Hypothesis": "There is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers." In 1900, Hilbert included the question of the Continuum Hypothesis in his list of 23 unsolved problems. 1882 Lindemann proves that Pi is transcendental. A corollary is the imposibility of squaring a circle with a compass and straightedge. 1883 Cantor publishes the Cantor Set, a rich source of counterexamples 1887 Poincare discovers the phenomenon of "Chaos" while studying celestial mechanics. There exist orbits that are neither unbounded nor limiting to a stable state. 1889 Peano publishes a set of axioms for arithmetic which are now the standard. 1898 Hadamard defines a dynamical system where all orbits exponential diverge from each other with a positive Lyapunov exponent. 1900 Hilbert publishes a list of 23 unsolved problems. They include: The Continuum Hypothesis (proved independent of ZFC by Godel) Prove that the axioms of arithmetic are consistent. (proved impossible by Godel) The Riemann Hypothesis (still unresolved) What is the densest sphere packing? (resolved in 1998) 1901 Russell publishes "Russell's Paradox", which shows that Cantor's set theory leads to a contradiction. This was resolved in 1922 by the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms of set theory. 1904 Lebesgue publishes the Lebesque Integral, a generalization of the Riemann Integral. "Lebesgue Measure" is the standard way of assigning a measure to subsets of n-dimensional Euclidean space. For n = 1, 2, or 3, it coincides with the standard measure of length, area, or volume. The Lebesgue measure of the set of rational numbers in the interval [0,1] is 0, and the real numbers on this interval have measure 1. The Cantor set is an example of an uncountable set that has Lebesgue measure zero. 1904 Poincare Conjecture published 1904 Zermelo defines the Axiom of Choice. Previously, mathematicians had been using this axiom implicitly without realizing it. Kronecker's opposition to Cantor's theories became the inspiration for the mathematical outlook of "Constructivism", which asserts that it is necessary to construct a mathematical object to prove that it exists (proving its nonexistence does not imply its existence). Constructivism is at odds with the Axiom of Choice and the Law of the Excluded Middle. 1922 Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms of set theory developed (ZF). This resolved Russell's Paradox. 1924 Banach-Tarsky paradox published, exhibiting a spooky consequence of the Axiom of Choice. 1931 Godel proves the Incompleteness Theorems. For any set of axioms that are nontrivial and consistent, there will exist statements about the natural numbers that are true but cannot be proven within the system. Also, the system cannot prove its own consistency. Cantor's "diagonal slash" argument was an inspiration for these theorems. 1935 Bourbaki textbooks published, with the aim of reformulating mathematics on an extremely abstract and formal but self-contained basis. With the goal of grounding all of mathematics on set theory, the authors strove for rigour and generality. 1940 Godel proves that the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be disproved with the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms (ZF). He also established that the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be disproved even if the Axiom of Choice is added to the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms (ZFC). 1961 Lorenz finds that computer simulations of weather have extreme sensitivity to initial conditions. 1963 Cohen proves that the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis cannot be proved with the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, establishing that they are independent of ZF. 1967 Mandelbrot publishes examples of fractals from nature 1967 Bishop publishes "Foundations of Constructive Analysis", where he proved most of the important theorems in real analysis by constructive methods. 1982 Mandelbrot publishes "The Fractal Geometry of Nature" 1983 Langlands Program published 1994 Wiles proves Fermat's Last Theorem 2000 Millenium Prize problems published. They include: The Riemann Hypothesis P versus NP The Poincare Conjecture Navier–Stokes existence and smoothness 2002 Perelman proves the Poincare Conjecture 2009 Chau proves the Fundamental Lemma for the Langlands Program 2013 Zhang and Maynard publish results that constitute progress toward resolving the twin prime conjecture.
f(1) = 0 f(2) = 1 f(3) = 1/2 f(4) = 1/3 f(5) = 2/3 f(6) = 1/4 f(7) = 3/4 f(8) = 1/5 f(9) = 2/5 f(10) = 3/5 f(11) = 4/5 f(12) = 1/6 f(13) = 5/6 f(14) = 1/7 f(15) = 2/7 f(16) = 3/7 etc.Every rational number corresponds to a unique integer and every integer corresponds to a unique rational number (a "bijection").
If a set can be bijected with the integers we say it is "Countable". The rational numbers are countable.
"Algebraic numbers" are numbers that can be expressed as the root of a non-zero n-degree polynomial with integer coefficients. The rational numbers correspond to roots of polynomials of degree 1. The algebraic numbers are countable.
Rational number Expressible as A/B, where A and B are integers. Irrational number Not a rational number. Algebraic number Expressible as the root of a non-zero polynomial with integer coefficients. Transcendental number Not an algebraic number.Suppose we attenpt to count the real numbers on the interval [0,1]. Let X=f(I) be a bijection between the positive integers I and the reals X, where every real number X is represented by some integer I. Let g(X,n) be the nth digit of X to the right of the decimal point. Define a number Z such that g(Z,n) = g(f(n),n). Z is not equal to f(I) for any integer I, and so Z is not present in the counting. Any attempt to count the reals will result in at least one missed number, hence the reals are uncountable. We say that the integers are "countably infinite" and the reals are "uncountably infinite".
This is Cantor's "diagonal slash" argument that he used to establish that the real numbers are more numerous than the integers. Godel's theorems are inspired by the diagonal slash argument.
In terms of subsets,
Integers < Rational numbers < Algebraic numbers < Transcendental numbersA countable set has Lebesgue measure zero. In terms of Lebesgue measure over the interval [0,1],
0 = Rational numbers = Algebraic numbers < Transcendental numbers = Real numbers = 1Two sets have the same "cardinality" if and only if a bijection exists between them. In terms of cardinality,
Integers = Rational numbers = Algebraic numbers < Transcendental numbers = Real numbersIn terms of cardinality, real numbers are infinitely more numerous than algebraic numbers.
The Continuum Hypothesis conjectures that there exists no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. If such a set S existed, its cardinality would be such that
Integers < S < Real numbers
Hermann Weyl, 1949: "Mathematics with Brouwer gains its highest intuitive clarity. He succeeds in developing the beginnings of analysis in a natural manner, all the time preserving the contact with intuition much more closely than had been done before. It cannot be denied, however, that in advancing to higher and more general theories the inapplicability of the simple laws of classical logic eventually results in an almost unbearable awkwardness. And the mathematician watches with pain the greater part of his towering edifice which he believed to be built of concrete blocks dissolve into mist before his eyes."
Hermann Weyl, 1939: "In these days the angel of topology and the devil of abstract algebra fight for the soul of each individual mathematical domain."
Poincare: "There is no actual infinite; the Cantorians have forgotten this, and that is why they have fallen into contradiction."